DCMI Note - On Information Factoring in Dublin Metadata Records
Title:
|
On Information Factoring in Dublin Metadata Records |
Creator:
|
Sperberg-McQueen, C. M.
|
Date Issued:
|
1996-04-17
|
Identifier:
|
|
Replaces:
|
NA
|
Is Replaced By:
|
NA
|
Latest version:
|
http://dublincore.org/specifications/dublin-core/info-factoring/
|
Status of document:
|
This is a DCMI Note.
|
Description of document: |
This document describes some problems in the interpretation of metadata records which contain repeated fields, repeated field groups, or references to other metadata records. The semantics of repeated fields and groups (and, equivalently, of references to other metadata records) are described using sentential logic, and a proposal is made to specify the interpretation of repeating groups using the disjunctive normal form of corresponding logical expressions. From this proposal, requirements for grouping elements and inheritance are derived. The semantic principles involved may be of wider applicability, but all examples are from the socalled `Dublin Core' of metadata elements, described in the paper OCLC/NCSA Metadata Workshop Report, by Stuart Weibel, Jean Godby, Eric Miller, and Ron Daniel, available on the World Wide Web at http://www.oclc.org:5046/conferences/metadata/dublin_core_report.html. |
|
Dublin Core™ Architecture Working Group: Discussion Note
Status of this Document
This document, first published in 1996, is being made available as a Dublin Core™ discussion note as part of the DC-Architecture Working Group's effort to formalise an XML/RDF representation of the Dublin Core™. While the document is 5 years old, many of the issues and observations made are worth reconsidering in the light of subsequent work on RDF and XML. The DC Note in its current form is UNPUBLISHED and undergoing minor edits for publication on the dublincore.org site. Contact Dan Brickley (dc-architecture co-chair) if you have any queries regarding this process.
The remainder of this document is unaltered apart from minor edits for XHTML validation.
On Information Factoring in Dublin Metadata Records
C. M. Sperberg-McQueen
17 April 1996
Table of Contents
- 1 The Problem
- 2 Semantic Models
- 2.1 Sentential Logic
- 2.2 Existential Quantifiers
- 3 Markup Solutions
- 3.1 Groups
- 3.2 Implicit Anding and Oring
- 3.3 Inheritance
- 4 Conclusion
This document describes some problems in the interpretation of metadata records which contain repeated fields, repeated field groups, or references to other metadata records. The semantics of repeated fields and groups (and, equivalently, of references to other metadata records) are described using sentential logic, and a proposal is made to specify the interpretation of repeating groups using the disjunctive normal form of corresponding logical expressions. From this proposal, requirements for grouping elements and inheritance are derived. The semantic principles involved may be of wider applicability, but all examples are from the socalled `Dublin Core' of metadata elements, described in the paper OCLC/NCSA
Metadata Workshop Report, by Stuart Weibel, Jean Godby, Eric Miller, and Ron Daniel, available on the World Wide Web at http://www.oclc.org:5046/conferences/metadata/dublin_core_report.html.
1 The Problem
The data elements defined for a metadata record by the `Dublin Core' are all optional and all repeatable, and have no prescribed order. Some (e.g. author, title) relate to the intellectual content of an object (the work), while others (e.g.form) relate to particular realizations or instantiations of that intellectual content. Some (e.g. identifier, terms and conditions) may apply to all forms taken by a given item, or only to some forms and not others.
For example, consider the documentation for the TEI Lite SGML tag set. As a work, it may be described by the following metadata:
- Title
- Form
- Form
- T = "The item has the title On the Pulse of
Morning." - A = "The item was written by Maya Angelou."
- P = "The item was published by the University of Virginia Library Electronic Text Center."
- D = "The item was published in 1993."
- etc.
Then the metadata record as a whole can be expressed formulaically:(T & A & P & D & OA & Ob & F & S & L)
, or "The item has the title On the Pulse of Morning and the item was written by Maya Angelou and ...". - T = "The item has the title TEI Lite: An
Introduction to Text Encoding for Interchange." - A1 = "The item was written by Lou Burnard."
- A2 = "The item was written by C. M. Sperberg-McQueen."
- F1 = "The item is in TEI Lite form."
- I1 = "The item has the URL _http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.tei_."
- F2 = "The item is in HTML form."
- I2 = "The item has the URL _http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.html_."
- I3 = "The item has the URL _http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.split.html_."
then the record as a whole has the following formulaic interpretation:(T & A1 & A2 & ((F1 & I1) | (F2 & (I2 | I3))))
, which can be paraphrased in English roughly thus: > - The item is called "TEI Lite: ..." - and it was written by Lou Burnard
- and it was (also) written by C. M. Sperberg-McQueen
- and it is
- either in TEI Lite as .../teiu5.tei
- or in HTML
- either as .../teiu5.html
- or as .../teiu5.split.html.
T & A1 & A2 & F1 & I1
T & A1 & A2 & F2 & I2
T & A1 & A2 & F2 & I3
i.e.- TEI Lite, by LB and CMSMcQ, in TEI Lite format, at .../teiu5.tei
- TEI Lite, by LB and CMSMcQ, in HTML format, at .../teiu5.html
- TEI Lite, by LB and CMSMcQ, in HTML format, at .../teiu5.split.html
- either the title is TEI Lite ...and the author(s) are LB and CMSMcQ and the form is TEI Lite the URL is .../teiu5.tei
- or the title is TEI Lite ...and the author(s) are LB and CMSMcQ and the form is HTML the URL is .../teiu5.html
- or the title is TEI Lite ...and the author(s) are LB and CMSMcQ and the form is HTML the URL is .../teiu5.split.html
- Each element in a metadata record represents a single logical predicate.
- A simple record is interpreted as the
and
-ing together (conjunction) of its sub-elements. - A complex record is interpreted as a shorthand for the
or
-ing together (disjunction) of several simple records, each represented by one term in the complex record's disjunctive normal form. - there are objects w, lb, cmsmcq, i1, i2, and i3, such that
- w is a work
- the title of w is TEI Lite ...
- the full name of lb is Lou Burnard
- the full name of cmsmcq is C. M. Sperberg-McQueen
- (an) author of w is lb
- (an) author of w is cmsmcq
- i1 is an instance of w
- the format of i1 is teilite
- the URL of i1 is .../teiu5.tei
- i2 is an instance of w
- the format of i2 is teilite
- the URL of i2 is .../teiu5.tei
- i3 is an instance of w
- the format of i3 is teilite
- the URL of i3 is .../teiu5.tei
- i1 and i2 are not the same object
- i1 and i3 are not the same object
- Replace the reference (virtually) with the contents of the referenced record (or, with those parts of the referenced record not overridden by local specifications).
- If the local record and the referenced record are both simple (in the sense given above), then the result is also guaranteed simple.
- If the local or the referenced record are complex, then the same rules of interpretation must be applied as for other complex records.
- if the SGML element is of type
, then create a new output record (which becomes the `current output record'): first copy the element itself, and then copy each of its children, following these same rules - if the element is of type
, then - copy nothing to the current output record
- for each subelement of the
, create a new output record, copying the subelement to the new output record following these same rules - at the end of each subelement's output record, add a reference to the current output record, with relationship-type of
inheritance
- if the element is of type
, copy the element itself to the current output record, renaming it as a element; then copy all its children, using these same rules - otherwise, copy the element using its current type, then copy all its children using these same rules
- Give the new record a name or URL; remember this name in the variable N.
- If any
elements occur as children of the root element, then delete the entire element and copy it into a new record. Add, as the first element in the new record, a reference to record N. Then process the new record as described in this procedure. (It gets its own name, etc.) - If any
elements occur as children of the root element, then remove the start- and end-tags from the element, thus promoting its children one level in the document tree. - record C (at
http://www.meta.org/catalog/c
):
<citation>
<title>TEI Lite: An Introduction to
Text Encoding for Interchange</title>
<author>Lou Burnard</author>
<author>C. M. Sperberg-McQueen</author>
</citation>
- record A1 (at
http://www.meta.org/catalog/a1
):
<citation id=A1>
<relation scheme='URL' type='OtherType' othertype='inherits'>
http://www.meta.org/catalog/c
</relation>
<form>TEI Lite</form>
<identifier scheme='URL'>
http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.tei
</identifier>
</citation>
- record A2 (at
http://www.meta.org/catalog/a2
):
<citation id=A2>
<relation scheme='URL' type='OtherType' othertype='inherits'>
http://www.meta.org/catalog/c
</relation>
<form>HTML</form>
</citation>
- record H1 (at
http://www.meta.org/catalog/h1
):
<citation>
<relation scheme='URL' type='OtherType' othertype='inherits'>
http://www.meta.org/catalog/a2
</relation>
<identifier scheme='URL'>
http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.html
</identifier>
</citation>
- record H2 (at
http://www.meta.org/catalog/h2
):
<citation>
<relation scheme='URL' type='OtherType' othertype='inherits'>
http://www.meta.org/catalog/a2
</relation>
<identifier scheme='URL'>
http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.split.html
</identifier>
</citation>
<dd>TEI Lite: An Introduction to Text Encoding for
Interchange</dd>
<dt>Author</dt>
<dd>Lou Burnard</dd>
<dt>Author</dt>
<dd>C. M. Sperberg-McQueen</dd>
</dl>
It has, however, three realizations with distinct URLs, one for the TEI version:
<dd>TEI Lite</dd>
<dt>Identifier (URL)</dt>
<dd>http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.tei</dd>
</dl>
and two for two different HTML versions:
<dd>HTML</dd>
<dt>Identifier (URL)</dt>
<dd>http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.html</dd>
<dt>Identifier (URL)</dt>
<dd>
http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.split.html</dd>
</dl>
How should, could, or must metadata for such items be represented?
At the Warwick meeting, Dan LaLiberte argued that in Dublin it was agreed that a given metadata record should describe only a single realization of an intellectual object; this would help ensure that metadata records are unambiguous. I don't find this explicit in the Dublin conference report, but that report does say explicitly that multiple versions may require multiple records. Redundancy may be controlled by factoring common information (e.g. work-related information) into separate records and `inheriting' it in the records for specific realizations. On this view, the three instantiations of the TEI Lite documentation will each require a separate metadata record.
Reports at the Warwick meeting (April, 1996) from users of the Dublin core, however, make clear that in practice, there is a strong desire to put metadata for a given work in a single record, using some mechanism such as repeating groups to describe multiple realizations. This paper, for example, might be represented thus with repeating groups (I use the DTD described by Eric Miller's paper Issues of Document
Description in HTML, available at http://www.oclc.org:5046/~emiller/tmp/paper.html. ):
<citation> <title>TEI Lite: An Introduction to Text Encoding for Interchange</title> <author>Lou Burnard</author> <author>C. M. Sperberg-McQueen</author> <form>TEI Lite</form> <identifier scheme='URL'> http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.tei </identifier> <form>HTML</form> <identifier scheme='URL'> http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.html </identifier> <identifier scheme='URL'> http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.split.html </identifier> </citation>
The only problem with this method is that it requires a lot of intelligence in the reader or user of the metadata to interpret the meaning of fields which occur more than once. A human may easily realize that the first form (TEI Lite) applies only to the first identifier, and that the second and third identifiers are for objects in the second form (HTML); software will realize it only if suitably instructed. A human will realize, perhaps even without conscious thought, that the two
The association of form and identifier information can be made explicit, using the
<citation> <title>TEI Lite: An Introduction to Text Encoding for Interchange</title> <author>Lou Burnard</author> <author>C. M. Sperberg-McQueen</author> <instance> <form>TEI Lite</form> <identifier scheme='URL'> http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.tei </identifier> </instance> <instance> <form>HTML</form> <identifier scheme='URL'> http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.html </identifier> <identifier scheme='URL'> http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.split.html </identifier> </instance> </citation>This is an improvement, but not a full solution (note, for now, that two HTML identifiers still require different interpretation from the two _
If common information is factored out into other records, we may be able to escape some of these logical difficulties, but we need a clear explanation of how information in the local record and the inherited information imported from an external record are to be related: are they always additive, even if the same field appears in both records? Or does a local field `override' the inherited value for that field?
2 Semantic Models
We can get a better grip on the problem if we apply some principles of formal logic. The simplest way to formalize the semantics of a Dublin metadata record, it seems to me, is using sentential logic. Existential quantifiers may also be used, and I describe that possibility briefly, enough to persuade myself that the more complex formalism does not require a more complex syntax for metadata records. Either approach allows us first to express more clearly the types of ambiguity arising from repeated fields or groups, and second to see what sorts of mechanisms might suffice to disambiguate them.
2.1 Sentential Logic
Let us consider first why a simple record like the following seems less problematic than the sample given above:
<citation> <title>On the Pulse of Morning <author>Maya Angelou <publisher>University of Virgina Library Electronic Text Center <otherAgent>Transcribed by the University of Virginia Electronic Text Center <date>1993 <object>Poem <form>1 ASCII file <source>Newspaper stories and oral performance of text at the presidential inauguration of Bill Clinton <language>English </citation>
The key difference, I believe, is that all of the metadata in this record unambiguously applies all the time, while some elements of the previous record apply only in conjunction with certain other elements.
If we express each element as a logical proposition, the simple record has a correspondingly simple logical form. For convenience, let us give each proposition a short name:
The more complex record has a more complex logical structure. If we name the propositions thus:
Each individual instance can be described (as Dan LaLiberte points out) with a simple metadata record, which translates into a simple formula:
I believe that this simple form of expression, in which the only connector is and
, corresponds to the class of metadata records which are unambiguous and easy to interpret. The problem of interpreting complex metadata records (ones with repeating fields or groups) can thus be paraphrased: how do we derive a set of simple and
-expressions from the logical expression representing a complex metadata record?
Fortunately, the answer is simple.
If we combine the three simple expressions into a single formula, we get a paraphrase of the metadata record as a whole:
( (T & A1 & A2 & F1 & I1) | (T & A1 & A2 & F2 & I2) | (T & A1 & A2 & F2 & I3) )which can be paraphrased roughly thus: > (if you have an item in hand described by this metadata record, then one of these three things is true:)
The salient point (and the only interesting or new claim in this entire paper) is that this expression is logically equivalent to the original formula for the example, but unlike the original this one is in disjunctive normal form.[1] It is fortunately not hard to generate the disjunctive normal form of arbitrary logical expressions, particularly when (as here) the only operators allowed are and
and or
.
We can then describe the semantics of metadata records thus:
We do need, however, a way to make explicit not only the parenthetical groupings in the formula (and
(&) and which by or
(|). We can see therefore that proposals calling for a single grouping element (such as that made by Eric Miller in the paper already mentioned, or by myself in informal DTD sketches) will not suffice to solve the problem. We need not one but two distinct types of group. Miller's and
-group, since simple citations are interpreted as the and
-ing together (formally, the conjunction) of their elements. It will have to be able to nest recursively, however, if we want to handle all cases of shared metadata. And we will need a second grouping element, to serve as an or
-group. For examples, see the section Groups, below.
2.2 Existential
Quantifiers</a>
Some readers may resist the use of sentential logic as a formalism for representing the meanings of metadata records in general, since the meaning of
<citation> <title>On the pulse of morning</title> </citation>is not, in general, merely "The title is On the pulse of
morning</cite>" but something more like "(There is an object, described by this record, and) the title (_of the object described by this record_) is <cite>On the pulse of
morning</cite>." That is, there is an implied existential quantifier inherent in the existence of a metadata record, and there is an implied argument for each metadata element, viewed as a logical function.
Paraphrasing records at this level of detail would make it easier to capture the semantics of work and realization more clearly. Represented in first-order predicate calculus, our example might look like this:
(E w)(E lb)(E cmsmcq)(E i1)(E i2)(E i3) ( work(w) & title(w,"TEI Lite ...") & name(lb,"Lou Burnard") & name(cmsmcq,"C. M. Sperberg-McQueen") & author(w,lb) & author(w,cmsmcq) & instance(w,i1) & form(i1,teilite) & url(i1,".../teiu5.tei") & instance(w,i2) & form(i2,html) & url(i2,".../teiu5.html") & instance(w,i3) & form(i3,html) & url(i3,".../teiu5.html") & (i1 != i2) & (i1 != i3) )which we might paraphrase as:
Note, in passing, that from the elements we can infer that the first instantiation is not identical to the second or third, but the second and third instantiations, both being in HTML, could conceivably be identical. Hence there is no claim that (i2 != i3)
.
If we are willing to assume that different instantiations are the only possible causes of or
-groups in metadata records, then we may plausibly believe (a) that complex metadata records can all be described with a single and
-group, if instantiations are given identifiers (such as the i1, i2, i3 of the example) and the identifiers are used to associate the metadata elements applying to each instantiation, and (b) that Eric Miller's or
-ed with each other, and nothing else will cause an or
group.
I'm reluctant to accept this logic, first because while many (all?) examples of logical complication in metadata records do involve multiple instantiations, I certainly haven't seen any argument that proves this is a logical necessity. Second, tempting though this argument is, I still don't know how to derive the formula just given systematically from the metadata record itself. The formula has three instantiations, and three form() predicates, while the metadata record itself has three
3 Markup Solutions
3.1 Groups
We saw earlier, when we used sentential logic to say what metadata records mean, that we need both a grouping element meaning and
and one meaning or
. The or
-group we must invent. For now, let's call it and
-group we already have, in the citation
element. The only drawback is that the term citation seems to imply that its contents constitute a complete citation, which will not always be the case. For purposes of illustration, therefore, let's invent a second new grouping element called
If we augment Eric Miller's DTD with
<citation> <title>TEI Lite: An Introduction to Text Encoding for Interchange</title> <author>Lou Burnard</author> <author>C. M. Sperberg-McQueen</author> <or id=O1> <and id=A1> <form>TEI Lite</form> <identifier scheme='URL'> http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.tei </identifier> </and> <and id=A2> <form>HTML</form> <or id=O2> <identifier scheme='URL'> http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.html </identifier> <identifier scheme='URL'> http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.split.html </identifier> </or> </and> </or> </citation>
3.2 Implicit Anding and
Oring</a>
It might be suggested (I suggested it myself, in the first draft of these notes) that we don't really need the
<and id=A2> <form>HTML</form> <identifier scheme='URL'> http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.html </identifier> <identifier scheme='URL'> http://www-tei.uic.edu/orgs/tei/intros/teiu5.split.html </identifier> </and>since the URL is a characteristic of the realization, not the work, and in general two identifiers in the same scheme will _always_ refer to distinct realizations. They thus might as well be regarded as forming a sort of automatic, implicit `or`-group.
On this view, some elements are implicitly and
-ed together when they repeat: author, for example. Some elements (e.g. identifier, form) are intrinsically incapable of being and
-ed together and thus form implicit or
-groups. Some elements can go either way: multiple titles may all apply, or they might apply each to one particular instantiation of the work (the French title applies to the French version, the English title to the English version of a European regulation, which might need juridically to be treated as a single work, since all national-language versions have equal authority).
On the whole, it seems better not to make too much of this generalization -- though it might be a useful heuristic for plausibility checking. Since some elements can go either way, we will need
It also is worth pointing out that the initial premise of this section is false: two URLs may very easily point to the same object, and it is easy to imagine methods of describing formats which would allow multiple names to be applied to the same format (just as in some programming languages the same data type can be referred to by multiple names).
3.3 Inheritance
There are three ways to treat inheritance of metadata from other records. We can insist that the inherited metadata never include the same elements as are present locally, or we can specify that locally specified elements override inherited elements of the same name, or we can attempt to specify some method of merging the two records so as to keep all the information from both records, by and
-ing or or
-ing corresponding elements together. In the first event, it may be overkill to speak of `inheritance'; in the latter, we may be reintroducing all the problems of repeating groups.
If we take the first or the second approach (or even the third approach, as long as we provide a simple rule, such as "All inherited data is and
-ed together with local data"), we will be able to interpret a reference to external metadata fairly rigorously:
By making liberal use of references to other records, we can do without
Or perhaps it would be clearer to put it this way: We begin by copying the entire
The sample record from the previous section would turn into the following set of records:
More work is needed here, I think, both to specify how to interpret the record when the same element occurs both locally and in the referenced object, and to specify what constitutes the same element.
4 Conclusion
An adequate syntax for multiple versions (realizations) of the same work (intellectual content) requires an explicit semantic interpretation, to avoid hopeless ambiguity. If we provide our syntax with mechanisms for both disjunctive and conjunctive groupings (and
-groups and or
-groups), we can provide simple rules for interpreting complex records in terms of their disjunctive normal form.
More complex semantic formalisms, using existential quantifiers, may also be defined, but do not require any syntax more elaborate than the simpler semantics.
Notes
[1] A formula in sentential logic is in disjunctive normal form if it is a disjunction (or alternation, or or
-group) of one or more terms, and if each term is a conjunction of one or more primitive sentences or their negations. No nested expressions are allowed. For a fuller discussion, any book on formal logic may be consulted, but perhaps the best discussion of disjunctive normal form and the algebraic manipulations used to achieve it may be found in W.V. Quine, Methods of logic 4th ed. (Cambridge, Mass. : Harvard University Press, 1982). [return to text]